Sunday, December 19, 2010

The Struggle for Fairness: Merit v. Need

The question of how to effectively employ the powers of the state to bring about a Fair Society is the "bread and butter" issue of all social and political philosophers. There are two underlying distinctions that cloud our understanding of the distribution of benefits and costs among humans: natural distribution and social distribution.

First of all, Nature provides all of us with a set of natural advantages and natural disadvantages that affect how we we fare in a Darwinian world. As John Rawls noted, these advantages and disadvantages are distributed based on a "natural lottery," which is partly genetic (lucky draw of genes) and partly social (lucky draw of parents and society). Given that nature "distributes" these advantages and disadvantages randomly, it's hard to argue that any of us "deserve" our current economic status. In other words, Mother Nature is not fair, because she blindly stacks the cards either in our favor, against us, or both. Therefore, social and political philosophers on the left, like Karl Marx and John Rawls, argue that the purpose of government is to use the coercive power of government to redistribute benefits and costs. Since merit (adaptive attributes such as high IQ and good looks) and need (maladaptive attributes such as low IQ and ugliness) are distributed unfairly, leftists argue that the purpose of government is to redistribute the fruits of the natural lottery. Call it: economic security.

So how do we go about this social redistribution process? Well, Aristotle identified four material principles of fairness: merit (the best get the most), need (the neediest get the most), equality (everyone gets the same), and utility (the distribution that affords the "greatest happiness for the greatest number"). Aristotle, a natural law theorist defended meritocracy, where all social structures are designed to make sure that the advantaged get the most and the least advantaged get the least: "the best get the most and the worst get the least." Any society that varies from this standard is unfair. He argued that the needs of the least advantaged are to be met by the virtuous acts (beneficence) of the meritocrats. But if neither merit nor need is deserved, neither is virtue." Not only did my parents pass on bad genes, they also failed to teach me virtue!" Therefore, how can I be held morally responsible for robbing that Quicky Mart last week? After all, I needed the money and the owner of the that store that I robbed inherited that successful business, along with a high IQ and good looks. So he didn't "deserve" that money, either.

Rawlians and Marxists solve this merit v. need struggle by using the coercive power of government to take a certain percentage of the store owners income and giving it to me, so I won't have to steal it in order to meet my needs. Marx (and B.F. Skinner) dismissed private property all together and argued that all goods are social goods, and therefore ought to be redistributed equally by a panel of government experts. Rawls argued that the most advantaged ought to be forced to contribute to a "basic safety net" or provide a social minimum to protect the least advantaged. Rawls, therefore, allows the most advantaged to prosper, but only as long as the social distance between the rich and the poor either diminishes or does not increase. The rich cannot get richer, if the poor get poorer as a result of a natural distribution.

So the common strategy employed by left-wing Marxists and Rawlsians is to use the power of government to eliminate or lessen the consequences of natural inequality. Now what do right-wing libertarians say about all this? Well, they present a long list of counter-arguments. Next time, I'll sketch in a few of them. Stay tuned.

2 comments:

Michael D. Donahoe said...

Love this blog Ron.

So I'm very curious how this will continue, but I would wonder if there isn't a stair step type answer to this.

I mean isn't the human conditions sort of to want more than what one has, and thus propels us to try and move up in the "predefined" social chain?

I think you could like the differences between from a higher class to a lower class to that of social maturity. Again this is predefined by social norms but statistically speaking most people don't "rise above" too far from their origins. This is as much to do with a local pull from peers as it has to do with one's own maturity and knowledge of their social environment I think. My point is this a matter of perspective - or relativity I suppose.

The poorest of poor does not compare themselves directly against the richest of rich. Everyone plays the game of keeping up with the Jones and holds themselves relative to the next step up and down. Feel free to correct me if I'm wrong here, this is likely more introspection than any research...so assumption could be damned here...

Anyhow, this is how I feel a Marxist society fails to capture as it misses the competitive nature of "I want to be distinguished by my peer" as opposed to trying to impose an equality over an entire mass of people.

I think there is danger in societies that have huge leaps in class systems where a perspective of fairness can not be obtained. When that occurs, a correction has to take place whether political or through natural economic measures.

Keep up the great work Ron!!

Freedom's Philosopher said...

Great points Michael! There's a lot to be said about the internal dynamics of competition. Are we competing with other humans in a quest for more time, energy, and/or resources, OR a we competing with ourselves; that is constantly striving to improve upon our own past?

It's also (I think) important to distinguish between time, energy, and resources. Personally, I have enough resources or money (other than a decimated retirement fund). At my age I would like more time and energy to do what I want. But I don't "consciously" compete with others. I don't compare my time, energy, or resources with others. I'm sure some people are hell-bent on "keeping up with the Jones'" but I'm not.

On the other hand, just because I don't think about competing with other doesn't mean that I'm not. At work, I could easily be replaced by a younger, smarter (more competitive) assistant professor that would willingly work for 2/3 my salary. So to answer your question...your relativity hypothesis may be correct.