What is torture? Well, first of all let’s all agree that
“torture” necessarily involves at least two persons; whereby one inflicts harm
on the other for various purposes. Hence we must distinguish between the
“torturer” and the person being tortured. Torture is a teleological or
goal-directed act; intentionally employed in pursuit of one (or more) of three main
purposes:
There are two main ways for interrogators to secure information from any sentient being: by employing “carrots and/or sticks.” Humans and other sentient creatures respond to both. Carrots are pleasure-based “enticements” offered in reciprocal exchange for information. Torture is pain-based. All persons with functioning central nervous systems tend to prefer pleasure-based experiences and avoid pain-based experiences. Some of us are capable of enduring higher levels of various kinds of physical pain for a longer period of time than others. Non-sentient beings that lack a central nervous system cannot experience pain (or pleasure) and therefore they cannot be enticed or tortured. Similarly, you won’t get much useful information by enticing or torturing comatose or brain dead prisoners. The same holds true for torturing dead persons: “Dead men tell no tales.” And, interrogators waste their time torturing masochists.
As stated at the beginning of this blog, most philosophical
debate is rooted in language. And, as Foucault has noted, there is a complex relationship
between “power and knowledge.” The CIA, a well-established power monger, employs
its own “private language” to distinguish between “torture” and what it calls “enhanced
interrogation.” Enhanced interrogation usually involves the use of lower-level,
physical harms such as the short-term deprivation of sleep, food, water, or
social interaction. These deprivations rise to the level of torture when
employed over longer periods of time. The CIA routinely admits that
it employs enhanced interrogation but it never tortures anyone. Philosophically,
we might argue over at what point deprivation becomes torture. Withholding food
for a day is different from withholding it for a week! Torture can also involve
the direct infliction of physical pain via exposure to extreme heat, extreme
cold, and or sharp objects. The key philosophical question here is at what
point does enhanced interrogation become torture and how does the torturer know
when to stop short of torture?
A few years back there was an extended public debate over
whether “waterboarding” of prisoners constitutes enhanced interrogation or
torture. The technique creates the “illusion” of drowning, but that experience
is non-lethal and non-permanent. But at what point does the experience of that
“illusion of drowning” become torture? How many times can an interrogator
“water board” a prisoner before crossing that line? How long per session? How
many sessions per day?
An interrogator might simply “threaten” to torture a POW. Sometimes
threats “work” very well, sometimes not. The key variable here is credibility.
The threatened POW must be convinced that that the would-be torturer will (in
fact) “follow-up” on that threat. If the Pope threatens to skin you alive…don’t
worry. Humans have other interests other than avoiding their own physical pain.
Thus, highly-skilled torturers often inflict (or threaten to inflict) physical
pain on third parties….especially the family and friends of the target. “If you
don’t talk NOW we’ll skin you and your family alive...family first.” However, threatening
to torture a POW’s enemies, is not really a threat but an enticement.
There are at least four epistemological questions that muddle
the contemporary debate over the use of torture in warfare.
First, does the POW
(in fact) “know” something of strategic value? If so, how does the torturer
know that the POW knows something of “strategic value?” Torture is obviously futile
in cases involving low-level combatants who don’t know anything. Competent
military leaders are very conscious of this fact, and therefore reveal
information to low-level soldiers on a “need-to-know” basis. Those who really
“know something” of “strategic value” are rarely found on the battlefield. In
wars involving decentralized enemies, where low-level combatants do not follow
orders from a central authority, torture is also of dubious strategic value.
Second, if there is (in fact) a high-probability that a POW “knows something,” is the information that is being sought by the torturer (in fact), of sufficient “strategic value” to outweigh the costs of using torture? Therefore, philosophically, we must unpack what is meant by “strategically important information;” and how to most effectively acquire it. The concept of “strategic value” is extraordinarily malleable, or “socially constructed.” It usually means that this information will help “win a battle” or “win a war.” But if a piece of information is (in fact) strategically important, one might also question whether torture is the most efficient way to acquire that information? Would the offering of enticements (such as: money, immigration privileges, better food etc.) be more likely to yield results? Moreover, torturing a POW in order to win a battle (short-term) might not, necessarily, win wars (long-term). In complex phenomena like warfare, cost-benefit analysis is inevitably dogged by unanticipated consequences. Sometimes losing a battle can be a short-term setback, but a long-term advantage; especially if it inspires recruitment of new, highly-motivated soldiers. Similarly, torturing POWs might inspire more enemy volunteers seeking retribution for torturing “their brothers.”
Third, if a POW
does (in fact) know something of strategic importance, does torture,
necessarily, yield useful information? If a torturer is waterboarding a POW who
doesn’t know anything, is that POW highly likely to lie in order to end that
torture? Most soldiers who know something are trained to lie effectively under
interrogation. What are the long-term costs of acting on false information?
Fourth, what would
be the sociopolitical, legal, or moral consequences of accidentally killing a POW
under interrogation? Would the opposing warring regime be more likely to torture
and/or kill POWs under its control in retribution? Therefore, does the use of
torture necessitate killing POWs that have been tortured, in order to prevent the
enemy from knowing that torture has been utilized? One might also reasonably
argue that the use of torture necessitates a shroud of secrecy? If so, is that
shroud consistent with a nation’s moral identity? If the United States hopes to
maintain its reputation as the beacon of Western democracy, how would public
knowledge of the use of torture affect that reputation? Is any “shroud of
secrecy” consistent with democracy? Do you really “blindly trust” the
institutions of government to operate behind that shroud? Do you trust congress,
the president, or the courts to supervise the CIA’s use of torture? If you are
a torturer, would you readily admit to your supervisors that you tortured that
prisoner, but didn’t get any information? If you are that supervisor, do you
REALLY want to know that your subordinate used torture? Wouldn’t you prefer to
operate on the basis of “plausible deniability” and be able to say “I didn’t
know that X was torturing prisoners? He was a ‘rogue torturer!’”
I’ll discuss the “Ethics of Torture” in my next blog.
No comments:
Post a Comment