This expensive book ($108) is intended to serve a small, but dedicated group
of scholars engaged in research on “transhumanism;” a subject that enjoyed popularity
in the 1980s and 1990s. Transhumanists are optimistic futurists who welcome
recent scientific and technological advancements in: “neuroscience,
neuropharmacology, life-extension, nanotechnology, artificial
ultraintelligence, and space
habitation.” (p.1) Most transhumanists are
also devoted fans of science fiction and/or spiritualism. Philosophers have
long-argued that the very concept of transhumanism is vague or vacuous and that
there has always been (and always will be) both defenders and critics of
present and future technology. Critics of transhumanism argue that unchecked, free-wheeling
scientific and/or technological advancement threatens not only the future of
humanity, but also the future of the entire planet. Therefore, they argue, government
must play a role in controlling that advancement: Keep that genie in the
bottle! For better or worse, this scholarly work is rife with “isms” that are
offered in comparison and contrast to “transhumanism,” including: neoliberalism,
futurism, utopianism, post-humanism, evolutionary utopianism, and xenofeminism.
With 200 pages of scholarly text, it is fully documented with over 600 footnotes,
citing mostly of books and journal articles published in the 1980s and 1990s.
By all measures, this is a book intended for a rather narrow community of
scholars. There is no obvious attempt to recruit new transhumanist scholars, no
appeal to a popular audience, nor is it intended to serve as an undergraduate
or graduate textbook.
Wednesday, November 8, 2017
Tuesday, September 5, 2017
Health Care Ethics Textbook
1. What is Health Care?
2-6. What is Ethics?
7. Informed Consent in Health Care
7.1 Liberty and the Childhood Measles Vaccine
8. Reproductive Ethics
9. Euthanasia and Suicide
10. Allocation of Resources
12. Affordable Care Act
2-6. What is Ethics?
7. Informed Consent in Health Care
7.1 Liberty and the Childhood Measles Vaccine
8. Reproductive Ethics
9. Euthanasia and Suicide
10. Allocation of Resources
What is "access" to health care? http://freedomsphilosopher.blogspot.com/2009/06/access-to-health-care.html
What is "quality" of health care? http://freedomsphilosopher.blogspot.com/2009/06/quality-of-health-care.html
What is "cost" of health care? http://freedomsphilosopher.blogspot.com/2009/06/cost-of-health-care.html
12. Affordable Care Act
Sunday, September 3, 2017
Reading #8: Informed Consent in Health Care
In health care, the concept of "informed consent" has two primary applications: Informed Consent in Research and Informed Consent in Treatment. In any Liberal Society these applications relate to the concept of "Human Agency," or the philosophical questions that underlie what kinds of persons can be held morally responsible for their actions. There are two conditions: rationality and free will. In health care two questions dominate moral and legal debate. 1.) Was the research subject or patient given enough information to make a rational choice? and 2.) Once provided with this information, does the research subject or patient, have the ability to act "freely" on the basis of that information... in short, does that person possess free will.
There are many conditions that might impede a research subject/patient's ability to process information. First of all: much of the language associated with health care is highly technical and derived from Greek or Roman nomenclature, and therefore most of us do not understand what the researcher or physician is saying. And most researchers/physicians have not been trained in how explain medicine in laymen terms. Therefore, many research subjects/patients are vulnerable, and rely on third-party agents, usually nurses. The most vulnerable classes include: young children, persons suffering from mental diseases, persons with very low IQs, persons with little education, persons that do not speak English, and elderly patients suffering from varying degrees of dementia. In these cases, proxies, or other rational persons must make those rational decisions. But who... family or friends, physicians, lawyers, judges, or juries?
There are also conditions that might impede a research subject or patient's ability to exercise free will, and consent to serve as a research subject or undergo costly, high-risk, medical treatments. Many potential research subjects/patients tend to defer these decisions to authorities who possess a Ph.D. or an MD degree. Many research subjects/patients are vulnerable to outside interference because they are desperately seeking to avoid and/or remove pain and or disability.
Informed consent has become an important moral/legal problem because researchers and physicians often have a stake in securing informed consent from prospective subjects/patients; and therefore may operate under a conflict of interest. Researchers need many research subjects in order to conduct clinical trials. Many researchers are college/university professors seeking tenure and promotion, researchers that are also pursuing lucrative patents for themselves or their respective corporation. Most physicians get paid for their services, and (like everyone else) needs to payoff student loans, feed, clothe, and shelter their families etc. Therefore, researchers and/or physicians might to tempted to misrepresent the known costs and benefits of serving as a research subject or undergoing an expensive treatment. Sometimes these misrepresentations rise to the level of legal fraud. Sometimes these misrepresentations are paternalistic, and therefore serve the greater interests of the subject or patient, but sometimes these misrepresentations are predatory and serve, primarily the interests of the researcher or physician. Research subjects may also be bribed into participation in a research project by offering either free health care or monetary reward. At what point does providing an incentive become bribery and/or economic predation (Kant)?
There are many conditions that might impede a research subject/patient's ability to process information. First of all: much of the language associated with health care is highly technical and derived from Greek or Roman nomenclature, and therefore most of us do not understand what the researcher or physician is saying. And most researchers/physicians have not been trained in how explain medicine in laymen terms. Therefore, many research subjects/patients are vulnerable, and rely on third-party agents, usually nurses. The most vulnerable classes include: young children, persons suffering from mental diseases, persons with very low IQs, persons with little education, persons that do not speak English, and elderly patients suffering from varying degrees of dementia. In these cases, proxies, or other rational persons must make those rational decisions. But who... family or friends, physicians, lawyers, judges, or juries?
There are also conditions that might impede a research subject or patient's ability to exercise free will, and consent to serve as a research subject or undergo costly, high-risk, medical treatments. Many potential research subjects/patients tend to defer these decisions to authorities who possess a Ph.D. or an MD degree. Many research subjects/patients are vulnerable to outside interference because they are desperately seeking to avoid and/or remove pain and or disability.
Informed consent has become an important moral/legal problem because researchers and physicians often have a stake in securing informed consent from prospective subjects/patients; and therefore may operate under a conflict of interest. Researchers need many research subjects in order to conduct clinical trials. Many researchers are college/university professors seeking tenure and promotion, researchers that are also pursuing lucrative patents for themselves or their respective corporation. Most physicians get paid for their services, and (like everyone else) needs to payoff student loans, feed, clothe, and shelter their families etc. Therefore, researchers and/or physicians might to tempted to misrepresent the known costs and benefits of serving as a research subject or undergoing an expensive treatment. Sometimes these misrepresentations rise to the level of legal fraud. Sometimes these misrepresentations are paternalistic, and therefore serve the greater interests of the subject or patient, but sometimes these misrepresentations are predatory and serve, primarily the interests of the researcher or physician. Research subjects may also be bribed into participation in a research project by offering either free health care or monetary reward. At what point does providing an incentive become bribery and/or economic predation (Kant)?
Saturday, September 2, 2017
Reading #9: Reproductive Ethics
Introduction:
Questions concerning the moral and legal foundations of human reproduction are enormously complex. Some of the most important questions have become public issues that address the following: the moral/legal limits of reproductive assistance, the moral/legal limits on contraception, moral/legal limits on reproductive control by individuals, religious groups, and political regimes; and a cluster of issues that involve abortion. All five moral principles (utility, beneficence, non-maleficence, liberty, and justice) are often invoked in reproductive ethics.
As an initial observation, let's all acknowledge that our individual and collective beliefs about human reproduction have been shaped by culture, religion, science, and politics. Today, all of these factors are also filtered through the media, especially social media.
Reproductive Assistance and Control:
Since the 1970s, reproductive assistance has been shaped almost entirely by both "low tech" and "high tech" reproductive technologies. Low tech include simple procedure such as artificial insemination, that employ little more than a glorified turkey-baster; high tech, include in vitro fertilization, sperm injection, and cloning.
Reproductive control includes who decides whether to have children, how many children, and on what basis might they decide, Hence "reproductive control" might include the use of contraception, the decision to continue a pregnancy, or abort a zygote, fetus, or infant, who decides and on what basis?
Three Moral/Legal Perspectives
Reproductive ethics in the United States is most often reduced to two extreme views: the EXTREME LIBERAL POSITION (Liberty-Based): Anything goes, individuals decide whether to have kids, how to have kids, how many kids to have, and whether to terminate pregnancies at various stages of development. No laws are necessary. And the EXTREME CONSERVATIVE POSITION (Natural Law or Roman Catholic View).
According to the Roman Catholic Church (via papal decrees), all sexual activity must take place within the "sanctity of marriage" between a male and a female via "natural" sexual intercourse." Three "sins" are to be avoided: sex outside of marriage (fornication) and sex outside of reproductive purpose via sexual intercourse (perversion), and abortion of a any fertilized ova, from zygote to birth. Thus, reproductive assistance within the church consists in making sexual intercourse more productive. Therefore, almost everything associated with In Vitro fertilization is regarded as immoral: donated ova and sperm, masturbation (to secure sperm), fertilization within a petri dish rather than within a uterus, and selective abortion in the case of multiple fertilized ova. Genetic testing, sex selection, gamete selection and storing frozen embryos are all regarded as an affront to "human dignity." In the case of blocked fallopian tubes, Roman Catholic fertility clinics may transfer those immobile embryos to the uterus.
There are a variety of what we might call "MODERATE POSITIONS that fall midway between extreme liberalism and extreme conservatism. Most reflect intermediary views on the status of the fetus and/or utilitarian concerns with IVF. Many libertarians regard zygotes a "persons subject to moral concern," others identify personhood with various stages of fetal development, usually the developmental stages where fetuses can experience pain and pleasure. Others, argue that abortion of fetuses that will lead a short life of pain and suffering may be aborted at the earliest stages of development. Others, accept infanticide as well. Utilitarians might object to the cost of reproductive medicine in an "over-populated" world and/or the inability to regulate reproduction in a global context.
Finally, it is important to distinguish between legality and morality. Libertarians tend to limit legal bans and mandates to major crimes such as murder, theft, and fraud. Many observe that fertility clinics commit fraud, when they "sell" IVF by overstating the likelihood that one or "cycles" of IVF will result in a "live birth," and that the cost of IVF is often obscured by charging patients per procedure, rather than per live birth. Many ultra conservative Roman Catholic scholars seek to legally ban IVF and abortion in all contexts, while others do not pursue legal bans and mandates for non-Catholics. Thus, many seek to distinguish between sins and crimes.
Problematic Technologies
In recent years several reproductive technologies have proven to be morally controversial: abortion drugs, genetic testing (for diseases, disabilities, and or sex), infant sex change operations, cloning, and the artificial uterus.
Questions concerning the moral and legal foundations of human reproduction are enormously complex. Some of the most important questions have become public issues that address the following: the moral/legal limits of reproductive assistance, the moral/legal limits on contraception, moral/legal limits on reproductive control by individuals, religious groups, and political regimes; and a cluster of issues that involve abortion. All five moral principles (utility, beneficence, non-maleficence, liberty, and justice) are often invoked in reproductive ethics.
As an initial observation, let's all acknowledge that our individual and collective beliefs about human reproduction have been shaped by culture, religion, science, and politics. Today, all of these factors are also filtered through the media, especially social media.
Reproductive Assistance and Control:
Since the 1970s, reproductive assistance has been shaped almost entirely by both "low tech" and "high tech" reproductive technologies. Low tech include simple procedure such as artificial insemination, that employ little more than a glorified turkey-baster; high tech, include in vitro fertilization, sperm injection, and cloning.
Reproductive control includes who decides whether to have children, how many children, and on what basis might they decide, Hence "reproductive control" might include the use of contraception, the decision to continue a pregnancy, or abort a zygote, fetus, or infant, who decides and on what basis?
Three Moral/Legal Perspectives
Reproductive ethics in the United States is most often reduced to two extreme views: the EXTREME LIBERAL POSITION (Liberty-Based): Anything goes, individuals decide whether to have kids, how to have kids, how many kids to have, and whether to terminate pregnancies at various stages of development. No laws are necessary. And the EXTREME CONSERVATIVE POSITION (Natural Law or Roman Catholic View).
According to the Roman Catholic Church (via papal decrees), all sexual activity must take place within the "sanctity of marriage" between a male and a female via "natural" sexual intercourse." Three "sins" are to be avoided: sex outside of marriage (fornication) and sex outside of reproductive purpose via sexual intercourse (perversion), and abortion of a any fertilized ova, from zygote to birth. Thus, reproductive assistance within the church consists in making sexual intercourse more productive. Therefore, almost everything associated with In Vitro fertilization is regarded as immoral: donated ova and sperm, masturbation (to secure sperm), fertilization within a petri dish rather than within a uterus, and selective abortion in the case of multiple fertilized ova. Genetic testing, sex selection, gamete selection and storing frozen embryos are all regarded as an affront to "human dignity." In the case of blocked fallopian tubes, Roman Catholic fertility clinics may transfer those immobile embryos to the uterus.
There are a variety of what we might call "MODERATE POSITIONS that fall midway between extreme liberalism and extreme conservatism. Most reflect intermediary views on the status of the fetus and/or utilitarian concerns with IVF. Many libertarians regard zygotes a "persons subject to moral concern," others identify personhood with various stages of fetal development, usually the developmental stages where fetuses can experience pain and pleasure. Others, argue that abortion of fetuses that will lead a short life of pain and suffering may be aborted at the earliest stages of development. Others, accept infanticide as well. Utilitarians might object to the cost of reproductive medicine in an "over-populated" world and/or the inability to regulate reproduction in a global context.
Finally, it is important to distinguish between legality and morality. Libertarians tend to limit legal bans and mandates to major crimes such as murder, theft, and fraud. Many observe that fertility clinics commit fraud, when they "sell" IVF by overstating the likelihood that one or "cycles" of IVF will result in a "live birth," and that the cost of IVF is often obscured by charging patients per procedure, rather than per live birth. Many ultra conservative Roman Catholic scholars seek to legally ban IVF and abortion in all contexts, while others do not pursue legal bans and mandates for non-Catholics. Thus, many seek to distinguish between sins and crimes.
Problematic Technologies
In recent years several reproductive technologies have proven to be morally controversial: abortion drugs, genetic testing (for diseases, disabilities, and or sex), infant sex change operations, cloning, and the artificial uterus.
Sunday, July 16, 2017
Reading #20: Consumer Privacy
We've already discussed Employee Privacy. Much of that conceptual framework carries over to Consumer Privacy, especially the distinction between private and public information.
First of all, the concept of "information" is epistemologically complex. The distinction between "public information" and "private information" is deeply rooted in Adam Smith's original distinction between "property" and "information." If there is a such thing as "private property," then why not "private information?" In what sense do individuals "own" information pertaining to their "private lives?" If there is a "right to privacy" is it a moral right or legal right? If there is a legal or moral right to privacy, then is that right a Positive Right or a Negative Right?
So if corporations have a duty to respect the privacy of consumers, what kinds of information ought to be kept private, who is responsible for keeping it private, and how do they do it. Some kinds of information are widely recognized as "private:" financial information, health information, sexual preference, preferred Internet sites, online purchases etc.
Stockholder Theory argues that, ultimately, it's consumers' responsibility to protect their own privacy, by limiting their communication to businesses that promise to protect that privacy. Health insurance companies need your personal health information in order to provide health insurance. Good health insurance companies would promise to protect that information via state-of-the-art information technology, or would consult patients before sharing with other third parties: employers, family members, the media, other sellers etc.
No laws are necessary. Companies that promise to effectively protect confidentiality, will attract buyers that value confidentiality. Companies that do not promise to maintain confidentiality, may attract buyers who do not care about confidentiality. For example, I often visit guitar sites, both guitars and playing guitars. I don't care if those sites share my guitar interests with other sellers. However, I'd rather keep most of my health-related information private, therefore I rarely post anything online that relates to my personal health. No governmental involvement is necessary. Over time the free market will protect privacy, to the extent that some buyers demand it in various contexts.
Stakeholder Theory argues that the free market often fails to protect consumer privacy, and that privacy can often be invaded without consumers even knowing that it is being invaded. Therefore, stakeholder theorists argue we need laws to protect consumers from the invasion of privacy, and the sharing (selling) of that private information to interested third-parties. For example, there are laws that protect the confidentiality of medical information. All providers are legally responsible for asking patients exactly who may have access to that information. The problem with these laws is that they make it difficult for friends and family to find out what's going on; and health care providers are forced to go through time-consuming, and resource-consuming bureaucratic lengths to provide the health care that patients want and need. Utilitarians might, therefore, argue that the costs of protecting consumer information far exceeds the benefits.
First of all, the concept of "information" is epistemologically complex. The distinction between "public information" and "private information" is deeply rooted in Adam Smith's original distinction between "property" and "information." If there is a such thing as "private property," then why not "private information?" In what sense do individuals "own" information pertaining to their "private lives?" If there is a "right to privacy" is it a moral right or legal right? If there is a legal or moral right to privacy, then is that right a Positive Right or a Negative Right?
So if corporations have a duty to respect the privacy of consumers, what kinds of information ought to be kept private, who is responsible for keeping it private, and how do they do it. Some kinds of information are widely recognized as "private:" financial information, health information, sexual preference, preferred Internet sites, online purchases etc.
Stockholder Theory argues that, ultimately, it's consumers' responsibility to protect their own privacy, by limiting their communication to businesses that promise to protect that privacy. Health insurance companies need your personal health information in order to provide health insurance. Good health insurance companies would promise to protect that information via state-of-the-art information technology, or would consult patients before sharing with other third parties: employers, family members, the media, other sellers etc.
No laws are necessary. Companies that promise to effectively protect confidentiality, will attract buyers that value confidentiality. Companies that do not promise to maintain confidentiality, may attract buyers who do not care about confidentiality. For example, I often visit guitar sites, both guitars and playing guitars. I don't care if those sites share my guitar interests with other sellers. However, I'd rather keep most of my health-related information private, therefore I rarely post anything online that relates to my personal health. No governmental involvement is necessary. Over time the free market will protect privacy, to the extent that some buyers demand it in various contexts.
Stakeholder Theory argues that the free market often fails to protect consumer privacy, and that privacy can often be invaded without consumers even knowing that it is being invaded. Therefore, stakeholder theorists argue we need laws to protect consumers from the invasion of privacy, and the sharing (selling) of that private information to interested third-parties. For example, there are laws that protect the confidentiality of medical information. All providers are legally responsible for asking patients exactly who may have access to that information. The problem with these laws is that they make it difficult for friends and family to find out what's going on; and health care providers are forced to go through time-consuming, and resource-consuming bureaucratic lengths to provide the health care that patients want and need. Utilitarians might, therefore, argue that the costs of protecting consumer information far exceeds the benefits.
Friday, July 14, 2017
Executive Compensation
The question of executive compensation is one of the more recent moral issues attract the attention of business ethicists. Here's the basic issue: "Are there moral constraints on how much corporate executives are paid?" The salient moral principles are utility, liberty, and justice.
Utilitarians argue that executive pay ought to be subject to the "greatest happiness principle:" or "the greatest happiness to the greatest number." Thus, there are consequences for both over-paying and under-paying executives. If the CEO is a utilitarian, then he would be inclined to
Stockholder Theory says that the CEOs primary moral/legal obligations are toward the owners of the company, the stockholders. Compensation of any given "executive" would be based on how much he contributes to the value of the company's stock. If that executive is (in fact) largely responsible for increased stock value, other companies might seek to hire that executive, and offer more salary, thus contributing to a bidding war. Thus, it's up to stockholders to determine "how to pay executives" and how much to pay executives." It is widely accepted among stockholder theorists that the interests of the stockholders and the executive must be aligned. So if any given executive (or CEO) earn more for the stockholders, the ought to pay him more. If not, they ought to pay him less. In the end, if valuable executives are under-paid, then they'll exercise the Liberty Principle and move to another company, when their contract has expired. If stockholders over-pay executives, there will be less money available to pay other employees, less money for advertising, less money for research and development etc. In the end, the Liberty Principle rules supreme, no governmental bans or mandates are necessary. The free market determines fairness.
Stakeholder Theory says that there is a social cost for overly-generous executive compensation. The more you pay executives, the less money you have left to pay other employees, financiers, and suppliers. Therefore, the CEO must take into account there other stakeholders. Some stakeholder theorists even defend the concept of a maximum wage, an objective limit on how executives are paid, and how much they are paid. Sometimes maximum wage might be set as a percentage of how much the lowest-paid workers are paid; maybe no more than 500% (5X) of the minimum wage. Others might argue, that all "raises" must be across the board, and that if an executive gets a 10% raise, so should everyone else. Of course, most stakeholder theorists would argue that there must be laws governing both minimum and maximum wages.
Today, executive compensation is often determined on the basis of cronyism; that is, the executives and the chairmen of the boards (stockholders) choose to reward one another, regardless of merit. Then, they disguise their mutual rewards behind a smokescreen legalese and/or verbal contracts behind closed doors. Stockholders, therefore, must insist on transparency, in order to minimize cronyism. The media often plays a role in exposing overly-generous compensation for both executives and board members.
Utilitarians argue that executive pay ought to be subject to the "greatest happiness principle:" or "the greatest happiness to the greatest number." Thus, there are consequences for both over-paying and under-paying executives. If the CEO is a utilitarian, then he would be inclined to
Stockholder Theory says that the CEOs primary moral/legal obligations are toward the owners of the company, the stockholders. Compensation of any given "executive" would be based on how much he contributes to the value of the company's stock. If that executive is (in fact) largely responsible for increased stock value, other companies might seek to hire that executive, and offer more salary, thus contributing to a bidding war. Thus, it's up to stockholders to determine "how to pay executives" and how much to pay executives." It is widely accepted among stockholder theorists that the interests of the stockholders and the executive must be aligned. So if any given executive (or CEO) earn more for the stockholders, the ought to pay him more. If not, they ought to pay him less. In the end, if valuable executives are under-paid, then they'll exercise the Liberty Principle and move to another company, when their contract has expired. If stockholders over-pay executives, there will be less money available to pay other employees, less money for advertising, less money for research and development etc. In the end, the Liberty Principle rules supreme, no governmental bans or mandates are necessary. The free market determines fairness.
Stakeholder Theory says that there is a social cost for overly-generous executive compensation. The more you pay executives, the less money you have left to pay other employees, financiers, and suppliers. Therefore, the CEO must take into account there other stakeholders. Some stakeholder theorists even defend the concept of a maximum wage, an objective limit on how executives are paid, and how much they are paid. Sometimes maximum wage might be set as a percentage of how much the lowest-paid workers are paid; maybe no more than 500% (5X) of the minimum wage. Others might argue, that all "raises" must be across the board, and that if an executive gets a 10% raise, so should everyone else. Of course, most stakeholder theorists would argue that there must be laws governing both minimum and maximum wages.
Today, executive compensation is often determined on the basis of cronyism; that is, the executives and the chairmen of the boards (stockholders) choose to reward one another, regardless of merit. Then, they disguise their mutual rewards behind a smokescreen legalese and/or verbal contracts behind closed doors. Stockholders, therefore, must insist on transparency, in order to minimize cronyism. The media often plays a role in exposing overly-generous compensation for both executives and board members.
Wednesday, July 12, 2017
Reading #23: Bribery and Corruption
Another problem
associated with the global market is the widespread use of bribery and
kickbacks in other countries. In most Western countries, offering a bribe and
paying a bribe are considered immoral, but the legal systems tend to treat the
offerers different from the payers. In many parts of the world, bribery is
regarded to be a necessary evil, a business expense, and the cost of doing business. Many cultures
regard gift-giving as a necessary part of establishing working relationships.
So, one of the initial puzzles is how to differentiate between a “gift” and a
“bribe.”
In many countries
bribery is regarded as tradition. Public officials in many countries are
routinely under-paid relative to market forces, and therefore they supplement
their income by taking bribes. Of course, there are small time petty “bribes”
by lower level public officials, and big time “BRIBES,” by higher level
officials. Is bribery always wrong, never wrong, or sometimes wrong? Are there
hyper-norms involved?
The most serious problem
with regulating bribery at a global level is that it is that it is almost
impossible to monitor and enforce laws against it. It takes place in private.
Bribes are often perceived by both offerers and payers as a business
opportunity, and therefore tend to perpetuate the tradition.
Conceptually, bribery
is a problem for both stockholder and stakeholder theorists. Stockholder
theorists tend to embrace “When in Rome do as the Romans do." But on the other hand, bribery obviously raise the cost of doing business, without adding to the value of the product or
service. Stakeholder theorists promote international laws that insist on corporate
“transparency” and laws that make it more difficult to pay bribes, especially
laws against money laundering. Stockholder theorists often argue that some of
these laws violate the right to privacy, or that these laws are costly and
ineffective.
Tuesday, July 11, 2017
Reading #18: Consumer Health and Safety
We already discussed Employee Safety in the workplace. What do business ethicists have to say about Consumer Health and Safety? Again, the two basic philosophical issues are: How healthy is a healthy product or service? And, how safe is a safe product or service. In short, what are the moral/legal standards?
First, let's admit that there are no products and services that are 100% healthy and/or safe. That's because, both health and safety are subject to both short-term and long-term utility. Eat a steak for dinner tonight, will certainly be a highly pleasurable experience; especially if it's accompanied by a couple of glasses of wine. There are also health benefits associated with eating red meat. Problems arise when consumers eat steak at every meal over a period of many years. Obviously, there is a financial cost associated with eating steak every day. But there are also health risks associated with eating large quantities of red meat over a long period including: cancer risks and heart disease risks. As for safety, eating steak carries with it a risk of choking, therefore, it is advisable that you chew your steak thoroughly before you swallow it.
There are also short-term and long-term benefits and risks associated with drinking wine. Over the short run, wine will aid in the pleasure digestion of food, but it can also be financially risky. If you drink more than 2-3 drinks, you are liable to get intoxicated, or at least intoxicated enough to crash your car and/or get a ticket for DUI. If you are pregnant, drinking alcohol poses a risk to developing fetuses. Over the long run you can also become an alcoholic, end up in prison, and ruin your family life.
So the basic issue remains: what are the moral/legal duties that accompany selling various products and services? Traditionally, most sellers willingly "warn" buyers of the most serious harms. Most alcoholic beverages are legally required to post a warning label that informs pregnant women that alcohol consumption might harm their fetus. Tobacco products are legally required have a warning label stating the risks of cancer and heart disease. Again, for business ethics, the main issue here is whether the government ought to force sellers to disclose all known harms or whether the free market will adequately inspire sellers to expose risks to buyers.
Stockholder Theorists argue that it's probably in the interest of sellers to share information about the health and safety of products and services. If they don't other third parties will do it, especially consumer groups and the media. However, labels are designed, primarily to attract buyers, therefore labels that are excessively complex, loaded down with minimum risks, are counter-productive: buyers are less likely to read a long diatribe. Once, buyers are warned of risks, the Liberty Principle guarantees that consumers have a right to take risks; and that State Paternalism violates the Liberty Principle.
Stakeholder Theorists are Kantians, and therefore argue all products and services ought to be as healthy and safe as possible, and that government ought to set those standards, monitor and enforce those standards. Some unhealthy and unsafe products and services are deemed illegal for everyone, others are illegal only for certain groups. When health or safety standards are violated, government punish sellers with fines and/or other legal sanctions. Stakeholder theorists tend to expand State Paternalism, by regulating what can be sold to whom. State paternalism is especially evident in laws that forbid and/or regulate: prostitution, gambling, and selling pot. Most Stockholder theorists argue that the more states regulate buying and selling, the fewer the buying opportunities, and the less happy we all are. In short, there is an inevitable tradeoff between legally imposed health and safety standards, the cost of products and services, and the happiness of consumers. I'll have another serving of steak and another glass of cheap wine. But I'll pass on the heroin and the prostitute. I don't need any advice or protection from government.
First, let's admit that there are no products and services that are 100% healthy and/or safe. That's because, both health and safety are subject to both short-term and long-term utility. Eat a steak for dinner tonight, will certainly be a highly pleasurable experience; especially if it's accompanied by a couple of glasses of wine. There are also health benefits associated with eating red meat. Problems arise when consumers eat steak at every meal over a period of many years. Obviously, there is a financial cost associated with eating steak every day. But there are also health risks associated with eating large quantities of red meat over a long period including: cancer risks and heart disease risks. As for safety, eating steak carries with it a risk of choking, therefore, it is advisable that you chew your steak thoroughly before you swallow it.
There are also short-term and long-term benefits and risks associated with drinking wine. Over the short run, wine will aid in the pleasure digestion of food, but it can also be financially risky. If you drink more than 2-3 drinks, you are liable to get intoxicated, or at least intoxicated enough to crash your car and/or get a ticket for DUI. If you are pregnant, drinking alcohol poses a risk to developing fetuses. Over the long run you can also become an alcoholic, end up in prison, and ruin your family life.
So the basic issue remains: what are the moral/legal duties that accompany selling various products and services? Traditionally, most sellers willingly "warn" buyers of the most serious harms. Most alcoholic beverages are legally required to post a warning label that informs pregnant women that alcohol consumption might harm their fetus. Tobacco products are legally required have a warning label stating the risks of cancer and heart disease. Again, for business ethics, the main issue here is whether the government ought to force sellers to disclose all known harms or whether the free market will adequately inspire sellers to expose risks to buyers.
Stockholder Theorists argue that it's probably in the interest of sellers to share information about the health and safety of products and services. If they don't other third parties will do it, especially consumer groups and the media. However, labels are designed, primarily to attract buyers, therefore labels that are excessively complex, loaded down with minimum risks, are counter-productive: buyers are less likely to read a long diatribe. Once, buyers are warned of risks, the Liberty Principle guarantees that consumers have a right to take risks; and that State Paternalism violates the Liberty Principle.
Stakeholder Theorists are Kantians, and therefore argue all products and services ought to be as healthy and safe as possible, and that government ought to set those standards, monitor and enforce those standards. Some unhealthy and unsafe products and services are deemed illegal for everyone, others are illegal only for certain groups. When health or safety standards are violated, government punish sellers with fines and/or other legal sanctions. Stakeholder theorists tend to expand State Paternalism, by regulating what can be sold to whom. State paternalism is especially evident in laws that forbid and/or regulate: prostitution, gambling, and selling pot. Most Stockholder theorists argue that the more states regulate buying and selling, the fewer the buying opportunities, and the less happy we all are. In short, there is an inevitable tradeoff between legally imposed health and safety standards, the cost of products and services, and the happiness of consumers. I'll have another serving of steak and another glass of cheap wine. But I'll pass on the heroin and the prostitute. I don't need any advice or protection from government.
Reading #17: Marketing Ethics
In the Western moral tradition, buying and selling involves marketing
of various products and services to various individuals and groups. Thus
advertising is an essential part of business enterprise. The longstanding idea
here that "fair" business transactions must be based on rationality and free will of
both buyers and sellers; that is, both must know what is being
offered and be able freely to reject or accept offers based on self-interest.
Historically, marketing certain kinds of products and services to vulnerable buyers (that lack either
rationality or free will) has been viewed as morally problematic. Potentially vulnerable
buyers include: children, poor people, sick people, desperate people, people that speak other
languages, and or old people.
Brain science now recognized two major systems in the brain
that are responsible for all decisions, including buying decisions: System I (fast decision-making) is
located, primarily, in the central regions of the brain which is responsible for
emotions. Marketing experts induce consumers to purchase various products and services by manipulating emotions: usually fear and sex. System II (slow decision-making)
is located mostly in the cerebral cortex and is responsible for slow, rationally-based
decisions. Marketing based on System II, pleads to consumer rationality, and therefore tries to logically convince consumers, by arguing that the benefits outweigh the costs.
Traditionally, business ethics has focused on System II, whereby buying decisions must conform to the principle of informed
consent, which means that forcing people to buy something they really don’t
want (by telling lies) is regarded as fraud in
the inducement a form of theft. Fraud usually involves the presenting false
information to buyers in order to sell a given product or service. It is an
intentional attempt to trick System II reasoning. A classic example of fraud
involves telling potential buyers that you are selling a Cadillac when it’s
really a Ford.
In recent years, a growing number of marketing strategies do not plead to rationality; but
rather plead to System I emotions. Marketing home security systems,
invariably, invokes the fear of strangers breaking into your home. Marketing
erectile dysfunction drugs, invariably depict good-looking elderly couples that
are about to engage in pleasurable sexual intercourse.
Effective marketing strategies usually involve
the manipulation of both systems. But what are moral/legal limits of marketing?
Are there limits on how far sellers can go in manipulating consumer rationality
and emotionality?
Stockholder Theory argues that marketing ethics is bound by
the Liberty Principle, and therefore rational competent buyers and sellers have
a moral and legal right to engage in business transactions, based on their own
self-interest. Its mantra is best described as “Buyer Beware.” Some buyers are cognitively
unable to “beware” because of diminished rationality or free will. Diminished
rationality might include low IQ, a lack of knowledge or education, or speaking
another language. Diminished free will might involve physical/emotional addiction
to various products and services, or the unwanted exercise of influence by
third parties. Buyers, who lack either rationality and/or free will, often make
purchases that others find irrational and/or harmful. In recent years, hoarders
have become increasingly common; that is buyers who are especially vulnerable to
System I and System II marketing. I have several friends who own 20-30
guitars, and cannot resist buying more. Do guitar stores have a moral
obligation to ask prospective buyer, how many guitars they already own? If they
already own 20 guitars, do those stores have a duty to refuse to sell them another one?
Or at least contact the buyer's wife? What if the buyer is a multi-millionaire and also owns 10 homes? Stock holder
theorists argue that sellers cannot reasonably, be held legally or
morally accountable, unless there is outright fraud committed. Unwise transactions
may, however, be subject to paternalistic intervention by other third parties; such
as parents, friends, adult children, physicians, and others. However, laws are necessary
only to the extent that they monitor and enforce rules against “fraud in the
inducement.” Therefore, at most, Stockholder theorists argue that potential consumers must be warned of non-obvious risks. False advertising, invariably involves either lying about the
quality or price of any advertised product or service. In the modern era, false
and/or misleading marketing is often revealed by private consumer groups and
the media.
Stakeholder Theory, argues that corporations have moral responsibilities
to consumers beyond the Liberty Principle. Therefore, marketing products and
services may involve other moral principles: especially, Utility,
Non-Maleficence, and Justice. One might argue, for example, that marketing
unhealthy breakfast cereals to children has contributed to our ongoing obesity
epidemic, and therefore, this negative utility ratio suggests that cereal
marketed to children violates the principles of non-maleficence and/or utility.
The same hold true the marketing of tobacco, alcohol, and/or firearms to
children. Sometimes toys are deemed unsafe for children of various ages. For
example, toys with small parts might present a choking hazard for infants. Toy
guns that look like real guns are also dangerous.
In a self-interested world dominated by mass communication
and computer technology, false advertising is probably inevitable. Indeed,
false advertising is partially supported by a longstanding traditions in
the advertising industry that condones the telling of "white lies"
in advertising. Sometimes these white lies make claims so outrageous that any
rational person ought to know that they are false. For example, the old
Keystone Beer commercials promised consumers a visit from the Swedish Bikini
Team. Soft drink advertisers promise to make our lives more exciting, vitamin
advertisers promise to make us feel and look younger etc. But the line between white
lies and black lies is not always very clear.
Thursday, July 6, 2017
Discrimination
Discrimination
is a violation of the formal principle of justice because it gives some
individuals more than they deserve and others less than they deserve. But if we
do adopt affirmative action policies, then some previously advantaged groups become
disadvantaged: in particular, white males. Some libertarians argue that reverse
discrimination also violates the formal principle of justice and therefore it
is equally wrong. In sum, the key philosophical questions raised by affirmative
action include:
1. In terms of public
policy, should government treat persons as individuals or as group members? If,
we are fundamentally group members, which group determines our identity? Am I
essentially unique individual or am I simply a white male? In other words,
should public policy be based on "impartiality" and be blind to the
attributes of particular individuals such as race, gender, age, or sexual
preference; or should it exercise "partiality" and help the
disadvantaged?
2. What role should
government play in mediating the competition for scarce resources between
groups and individuals? Should government simply guarantee the freedom to
compete, or should it redistribute resources based on moral principles such as
merit, need, equality, or social utility? Do individuals or groups have only a negative
right to compete for resources,or do they also have a positive right to
possess at least some resources?
3. What role should
government play in fighting economic effects of racism, sexism, and other forms
of prejudice?
4. Should public
policy aim at utility (preventing future injustice) or retribution (paying back) groups
and individuals that have suffered injustice in the past?
5. Does the Principle of Liberty, at least sometimes, trump the Principle of Justice?
Friday, June 16, 2017
An Introduction to “Nudge Science” and the Ethics of Influence
Ronald
F. White, Ph.D.
Mount
St. Joseph University
Department
of Philosophy
Mount St. Joseph University
Let’s begin by addressing the
most obvious question. Given the vast number of books published on political
science every year, why would the Association for Politics and the Life Science
(APLS) and it’s journal Politics and the
Life Sciences (PLS) expend time, energy, and resources publishing a
multiple-author analysis of a book that contains little (if anything) about the
life sciences, Darwin, or evolution? The answer is that The Ethics of Influence provides an excellent opportunity for APLS
to further expand its commitment to interdisciplinarity; especially, behavioral
economics.
Cass R. Sunstein, a prolific
author, has written several books and scholarly articles defending “libertarian
paternalism.” (Sunstein 2008, 2014, 2016, 2017) Libertarian critics have long-argued
that the conjunction of “libertarian” and “paternalism,” is oxymoronic; and
that the “liberty principle” or the “principle of autonomy” excludes
paternalistic intervention on behalf of rational, competent adults. Over the
years, with varying degrees of success, Sunstein has addressed many, if not
most lines of criticism emanating from both the political left and right. And,
like many scholars, his views have evolved, over time, based on that criticism.
This roundtable review will focus on the arguments presented in most recent
book and how those arguments may (or may not) apply to recent public policy issues.
By way of introduction, I will introduce some of the more enduring elements of
the conceptual framework that underlies Nudge Science; most notably, the
concepts of: choice architecture; political bans, mandates, and influence,
political ethics, and paternalistic intervention.
Choice Architecture
In recent years, the philosophical debate over
“free-will v. determinism” in the context of human decision-making has been
usurped by the social and biological sciences. Sunstein, a pioneer in the field
of behavioral economics, has consistently argued that human decision-making is
“framed” by “choice architecture;” a set of causal variables that influence (if
not determine) our ultimate decisions. We are not always aware of this framework and
therefore we often confuse “freedom to choose” with “freedom to choose within
architectural constraints.”
Given the vast number of architectural
variables that shape our ultimate decisions, one might still question how much
room is left for freedom of choice? But, for now, let’s leave these
metaphysical arguments for those lingering pre-scientific philosophers.
Today, philosophical
analysis initially focuses on clarifying the meanings of key concepts. In
ordinary language we use the term “influence” in many different contexts. In
physics, scientists use it to indicate natural causal relationships between
non-living things; that is, the sun “influences” the orbit of the earth. Biologists
employ the same term to describe a wide variety of relationships between living
things and their environment. And finally, in the human sciences we use the
term influence to designate a wide array of relationships between humans; but
not without risking confusion between causality with influence.
At least some of the choice
architecture that underlies our decision-making is contextual, and therefore
shaped by our own individual or collective life history and/or unique genetic
makeup. Interpersonal influence can be exercised between individuals (family,
friends, and/or strangers) or between collective organizations (businesses
and/or governments). However, “Nudge Science,” seeks to identify the (more or
less) universal psychological forces that constitute human choice architecture.
Sunstein and others argue that, scientific knowledge of these universal
mechanisms will improve our own individual decision-making by exposing our own natural
biases. But it will also advance our individual and collective ability to
influence the behavior of others (hopefully for the better); and perhaps even
increase our own ability to resist unwanted interpersonal influence.
One way to explore the
relationship between choice architecture and our ultimate choices is to analyze
a few relatively simple, clear-cut case studies. For example, we all agree that
our decision whether or not to go on a picnic on any given day is influenced (or
nudged) by the external physical environment, especially the weather. In short:
“nature nudges.” (Sunstein, 2016: 35) However, there may be conflicting opinions
of what constitutes good and bad picnic weather. My personal rule of thumb
would be: “the hotter the better.” In the case of conflicting weather
predictions, our would-be picnickers might “trust” one local forecaster more than
another. If it turns out to be unexpectedly cold and/or raining on the day of
the picnic, the availability of a picnic shelter may be turn out to be highly
influential, if not decisive.
Although nature and the external
physical environment, obviously, influence many of our decisions, it does not,
necessarily, determine those decisions. That’s because our decisions may also be
influenced by external social and/or political variables. Our decision to
picnic at any given park might also be externally influenced by legal bans and legal mandates. Many public parks legally ban the consumption of
alcohol, or legally mandate dogs to be on leashes. Hence, consumers of alcohol
and/or dog owners might choose one park over another based on legality. But all
legal bans and mandates require monitoring and enforcement, which require a
costly, ever-vigilant police force, and judiciary. Depending on whether a local
government is willing and/or able to monitor and enforce these legal bans and
mandates, those laws might be undermined by a “black market effect,” whereby would-be
picnickers might deliberately choose to violate those bans and mandates. In
fact, many utilitarians follow Sunstein and argue that it’s often more cost
effective for political leaders to exercise influence over citizens, rather to monitor
and enforce legal bans and mandates.
While our choices are obviously
“framed” by external physical and sociopolitical architecture, those choices
are also influenced by internal, psychological forces. Psychologists now agree
that human decisions are ultimately shaped by cognitive operations that have
evolved over millions of years, which are located in specific regions of the
human brain. System 1 cognitive
operations are “fast, automatic, and intuitive;” which include perceptual
and emotive operations. They tend to be associated with the parts of the brain
responsible for perception (back) and part responsible for emotive responses
(inner). System 2 cognitive operations
are “slow, calculative, and deliberative.” (Sunstein, 2016: 28) “Rational” operations
emanate from the frontal lobes or cerebral cortex. As scientific knowledge of System
1 and System 2 operations advance, so will our individual and collective ability
to influence and/or manipulate the behavior of others. However, that same
knowledge might also advance our ability to resist unwanted political influences.
The long-term challenge for Nudge Science is to distinguish between universal
choice architecture that underlies all human decision-making, from architectural determinants that are
contextual, and/or relative to specific individuals and cultures.
Historically, the most obvious
applications for Nudge Science have been in the domain of business marketing;
as the most successful business leaders have long employed knowledge of various
cognitive operators in order to more effectively market their products and
services to consumers. Sunstein and others seek to expand the exercise of
influence into politics.
Political Bans, Mandates, and Influence
Worldwide, political regimes
tend toward either authoritarianism or democracy. For better or worse, all
regimes exercise both coercive force and influence over citizens. Authoritarian
regimes rely almost entirely on coercive force, by monitoring and enforcing
legal bans and mandates; which often dictate, not only what is good, but also
how to pursue it. So what are the moral limits to the exercise of political influence
within liberal democracies?
Although Democratic Republics respect individual autonomy, they
also employ combinations of political coercion (bans, mandates) and political
influence (System 1 and System 2 Nudges). However, unlike Authoritarian
regimes, Republican regimes must morally justify bans, mandates, and nudges. For
example, most Western democracies employ System 2 nudges that mandate that private
corporations conduct scientific research on the costs and benefits of the
products and services they offer; and clearly and accurately “label” those
products so consumers can make informed decisions whether to purchase those
products or services. In the U.S. recent labeling proposals include mandating labels
that identify Genetically Modified Foods (GMOs) and labels that disclose the
caloric and sodium content of foods. As a general rule, most of us do not
object to labeling nudges. There are also Public Education nudges, whereby
governments mandate that corporations provide information concerning the risks
associated with dangerous or unhealthy activities such as smoking, drinking, distracted
driving, and childhood obesity. Again, most of us do not object to Public
Education Nudges based on System 2.
However, sometimes
governments supplement System 2 nudges with System 1 nudges, by requiring graphic
labels that instill fear of dangerous products. Fear is a powerful motivator.
Other System 1 nudges are based on universal perceptual defaults, including our
natural preferences for products presented at eye-level, and our inclination to
choose the first alternative. Therefore, many democracies mandate that cafeterias
present unhealthy, high caloric deserts at the end of the line, below eyelevel,
in less conspicuous places. Although most of us oppose health-related bans and
mandates, we often appreciate, or at least tolerate, health-related nudges.
Most of us are also naturally wired by choice architecture (individually
and collectively), to maintain the status quo, as evidenced by the formation of
personal habits and cultural traditions. Both habits and traditions are
notoriously difficult to change. That’s why we also have a propensity to avoid
making life-changing decisions. Many liberal democracies, therefore, mandate
that we make choices, such as deciding whether to be an organ donor before
getting a license. Other democracies employ Automatic Enrollment via default
decisions, which offer passive “opt-out” benefits rather than active “opt-in”
benefits, such as enrollment in Pension Plans or the use of Green Energy
options. We are also naturally programmed more to avoid harm, than to pursue
benefits. This explains why governments, worldwide, invoke fear rather than
merely promise a better life.Finally, we are also naturally predisposed to act in pursuit of short-term benefits, and avoidance short-term harms; less inclined to pursue long-term benefits or avoid-long term harms. In part, that’s why System 2 scientific arguments that warn of long-term harms associated with obesity, poverty in old age, breast cancer, and global warming, tend to fall on deaf ears. All of this suggests that System 2 nudges must occasionally be supplemented by System 1 nudges, and even bans and mandates.
Political Ethics
Much human behavior is
teleological (or goal-directed) and therefore, requires the analysis of both
means and ends. Empirical psychologists describe what human beings, in fact,
pursue (ends) and how they pursue those ends (means). Ethicists, however, prescribe
not only the ends that we all ought to pursue, but also how we ought to pursue
those ends. As a libertarian, Sunstein embraces the idea that liberty consists
in the freedom to choose which ends are worth pursuing, as long as that pursuit
does not harm others. Therefore, the Ethics
of Influence limits the application of Nudge Science to helping us achieve
the universal ends that all humans value. Sunstein argues that unlike “ends
nudges” (which dictate what we ought to pursue) “means nudges” are (by definition)
“freedom preserving.” (Sunstein,
2016:
Ethics, like psychology, political
science, and economics, is a scholarly discipline. For centuries, theologians
and philosophers dominated that discipline. The Western Legal and Moral
Tradition focuses on both “knowing” (what to do or not to do) and being willing
or able (to do or not do it). Thus the determination of moral responsibility
for one’s actions involves both rationality (the ability to know what’s right
and what’s wrong) and free will (the ability to do what’s right and not do
what’s wrong. The ability to “know” is widely regarded as a System 2 brain
function and the ability to “do” is usually considered to be a product of
System 1. For centuries moral
philosophers argued that ethical behavior is determined by either System 1 “feelings”
or System 2 “knowledge.” Historically ethicists argued over whether ethics is
anchored in System 1 emotions or feelings or System 2 rationality? Today we know it’s both.
Philosophers have also long-debated
the role that moral rules and/or principles play in moral decision-making.
Political philosophers have also questioned the degree to which liberal democracies
ought to rely on legality (laws) and morality (moral rules). Sunstein identifies four values, or “foundational commitments”
that constitute the ethics of political influence in a liberal democracy:
welfare, autonomy, dignity, and self-government. (Sunstein. 2016: 25) However,
the simultaneous advancement of all four values is often problematic. In a
liberal democracy (Republic), self-government often trumps welfare, autonomy,
and dignity. Therefore, unpopular bans, mandates, and nudges carry with them a
political cost.
Sunstein’s four commitments
are non-controversial and deeply embedded in the Western liberal tradition.
However, many philosophers would amend that list to include utility, justice,
or non-maleficence. Others might question whether his four commitments
logically independent. For this review
we’ll, assume that these four principles capture the essence of morality in a
modern liberal democracy. Given these four moral commitments, how might the
U.S. government go about justifying the deployment of specific bans, mandates,
and nudges?
Recall that political
scientists have long observed that authoritarian political regimes rely almost
exclusively on coercive force; in the form of “bans” (Don’t do X or you’ll be
punished by the state!) and “mandates” (Do Y or you’ll be punished by the state!)
Democratic regimes, in contrast, set
moral and/or legal limits on the use of coercive force. Left-leaning democratic
regimes tend to emphasize human welfare, often at the expense of autonomy, and
self-government. Sometimes welfare-liberals are even willing to employ coercive
bans and mandates in pursuit of welfare. Right-leaning political philosophers,
in the libertarian tradition, value autonomy and dignity over both welfare and
liberal democracy. For Sunstein, the battleground lies in the ethics of state
paternalism.
The Ethics of State Paternalism
In his classic work book, On Liberty, John Stuart Mill, laid the
conceptual foundation for anti-paternalism in liberal democracies. He argued
that the only justification for the use of political force (legal bans and
mandates) is to prevent or remove “harm to others.” However, “harm to self” by
rational competent adults is protected by the liberty principle. According to
Mill, paternalistic intervention by government officials must be limited by the
above “very simple principle.” The first step is to determine whether that potential
beneficiary is a rational, competent adult. If so, then that official may also
inquire whether that person, knows that this action will (in fact) result in
harm to self. If so, that official may present rational argument in order to
change his mind. But ultimately, physical coercion must be avoided. Thus,
according to Mill, paternalistic intervention on behalf of rational competent
adults must be limited to the determination of System 2 competence. If that
person is a rational competent adult, then paternalistic intervention must be
limited to providing information and issuing a warning. Sunstein seeks to soften
Mill’s anti-paternalistic stance based on state-of-the-art behavioral science.
There are three longstanding
philosophical problems are associated with anti-paternalism: an epistemic
problem, a moral agency problem, and the impure paternalism problem. The first
two problems are deeply embedded in the Western liberal tradition, which says
that rational, competent adults must be treated as “moral agents,” who can be
held legally and morally responsible for their actions toward themselves or
others. The third problem is the direct result of the corporatization of
welfare.
The epistemic problem arises
from the fact that “human agents” (rational, competent adults) may not “know”
(for lack of information) what’s good to do in order to promote their own well-being
(do exercise), or what not to do (don’t smoke). Libertarians, in the John
Stuart Mill tradition, argue that once a rationally competent adult is informed
(warned) of the self-regarding risks associated with any activity, government
cannot forcefully interfere with that informed choice. But how much information
does a rational, competent, adult need in order to make a truly informed
self-regarding decision? What should that paternalistic governmental official
do, if there is conflicting public information concerning the degree and/or
probability of a specific activity? How much information does a rational, agent
need, before he/she engages in a self-harming activity, such as smoking? If a
genetic test were available that might “inform” that would-be smoker of his/her
own cancer risk, and that would-be smoker refuses to take the test, is that
person really informed? Should government sometimes mandate those tests?
Moral agency is usually ascribed to rationally competent
adult humans. Thus, human agency hinges on the standards of knowing and doing. Even
if a rational person knows” what’s good for him/her (do exercise, don’t smoke),
that person may not be willing or able to do or not do it. Informed moral
agents might freely choose to smoke because “by their own lights” the immediate
pleasure of smoking outweighs the long-term health risks. In short, a person
may know what to do or not do, but will not or cannot do it or not do it. Some
humans obviously lack moral agency, including young children and/or adults;
who, by their very nature, lack rationality or free will. Today, given a
widespread explosion of conflicting scientific information that is readily
available; rational competent adults may be regarded as de facto incompetent. Many
substances and activities are now regarded as addictive, including: tobacco, alcohol,
heroin and even gambling. Addiction is widely regarded a mental and/or physical
disease, that justifies paternalistic medical intervention. Thus the
battleground lies in the question of whether person P knows what to do, and if so,
can person P do it? As psychologists continue to plumb the depths of choice
architecture, the more difficult it will become to defend absolute standards of
moral agency. The third problem is impure paternalism, whereby paternalistic
intervention by the state (in the form of bans, mandates, and nudges) benefits
not only the intended beneficiary, but other third parties, who benefit by providing
that benefit or removing that harm. Sometimes these third-parties are
governmental officials, or their friends or relatives; and sometimes they are
for-profit private businesses, non-profit charitable organizations. Americans often
object to impure paternalistic interventions that provide minimal benefit to
the intended beneficiary, while providing enormous benefits to third parties. In
recent years, the Affordable Care Act included both an employer and employee
mandate to purchase costly health insurance. That mandate has proven to be
increasingly unpopular among small businesses and young healthy workers.
Summary and Conclusion
In sum, many (if not most) humans
lack the intellectual capacity to acquire and/or process the vast amount of information
that is now available. And many lack the will to act upon that information. Many
instances of state paternalism benefit third-parties. This sets us up for the
basic issue that underlies the Ethics of
Influence: Is Mill’s anti-paternalistic stance still justified? Is
paternalistic intervention exercised by the leaders of left-leaning liberal
democracies ever morally justified? If paternalistic intervention is sometimes
justified, under what circumstances might liberal democracies violate autonomy
and/or, dignity in pursuit of welfare? The answer lies in self-government. Liberal
democracies must refrain from the deployment of political bans, mandates, and
influence that are enormously unpopular. In Appendix A (204-208) Sunstein lists
34 nudges and their corresponding approval ratings, which range from 86%
approval for Mandatory Labels for GMOs to 21% approval rating for “Default
assumption of Christianity for census data.” Liberal Democracies must also be
wary of paternalistic interventions that line the pockets of third parties;
most notably corporations that generously contribute to political campaigns.
In the final analysis, The Ethics of Influence is NOT about freedom
and determinism. The fact is that our all of our decisions are influenced by choice
architecture. Sunstein’s goal is to determine whether liberal democracies ought
to employ freedom-diminishing bans and mandates or freedom-preserving nudges.
Those decisions, he argues, ought to be made in conjunction with moral values: welfare, autonomy, dignity, and self-government. When
the deployment of influence is morally/legally justified, then leaders must,
then, decide which kinds of “nudges” (System 1 or System 2) are morally
justified and/or efficient? As nudge science advances, the exercise of political
influence by liberal democraciesmay become increasingly more efficient. The Ethics of Influence is all about when to
mandate, ban, or influence. If nudges are morally required or morally
permitted, what kinds of nudges are best employed in various contexts, and for
how long?
So how might recent advances
in Nudge Science be applied in addressing some of todays’ most vexing public
policy issues in the United States, including: obesity and dietary nudges, post-employment
poverty and retirement savings nudges, breast cancer and mammogram screening
nudges, and environmental degradation and environmental nudges?
References
Sunstein,
Cass R.; Thaler, Richard (2008). Nudge:
Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New Haven,
Connecticut: Yale University Press.
Sunstein,
Cass R. (2013). Simpler: The Future of
Government. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Sunstein, Cass R. (2014). Why
Nudge?: The Politics of Libertarian Paternalism (The Storrs Lectures
Series). Yale University Press.
Sunstein,
Cass R. (2016) The Ethics of Influence:
Government in the Age of Behavioral Science. New York, Cambridge University
Press,
Sunstein,
Cass R. (2017) Human Agency and
Behavioral Economics: Nudging Fast and Slow (Palgrave Advances in
Behavioral Economics) Switzerland: Palgrave McMillan.
David
V. Johnson (2017) “Twilight of the Nudges: The Quest to Keep Behavioral
Economic in Policy After Obama’s Presidency.” New Republic https://newrepublic.com/article/138175/twilight-nudges
Sunstein, Cass R. and Richard Thaler
“Libertarian Paternalism” The American
Economic Review. Vol 7 Number 2 ( May 2003) pp. 175-179
Friday, June 2, 2017
Virtue-Based Moral Theories
Most of the discussion so far in this book has related
to moral theories that were articulated in the late eighteenth century. But
moral theory has been around a lot longer than that. In the Western world (and
the Eastern World) there is a venerable system of moral reasoning based on the
idea of virtue. Let’s call those various systems virtue-based moral systems. In the history of Western moral theory,
there are two different types of virtue-based systems. The non-secular line of
inquiry relies on divine command theory in order to discern moral virtues from
vices, as illustrated by the Judeo-Christian moral tradition. The secular line
of inquiry relies primarily on reason and experience, and not divine command
theory. It goes back to the ancient Greeks, via the writings of Homer, Hesiod,
Plato, and Aristotle. The particular virtues espoused by non-secular and
secular theories are often contradictory; therefore it’s hard to discern the
common thread that binds these two virtue-based systems. But I’ll try.
First of all, all virtue-based systems tend elevate community over individuals. Therefore, they tend more toward communitarianism than individualism. Secular virtue-based systems usually identify communities with political regimes. In the case of the Greeks, it was the city-state. Judeo-Christian non-secular virtue-based systems theorists identify with religious communities.
For both the non-secular and secular traditions, the virtue of something refers to its excellence: something that performs its function well. So anything subject to degrees (good, better, and best etc.) has its virtue. Hence, virtue determines status within a prescriptive hierarchy. Although we can talk about the virtue of a specific kind of computer over others, the Greeks most often referred to virtue as excellence of human character and behavior. Aristotle differentiated between two spheres of human activity that are governed by virtue: the intellectual sphere and the social or political sphere. Intellectual virtues reflect excellence of thought (wisdom etc), while moral virtues reflect excellence of human behavior (courage etc.) Hence, Aristotle, a hedonist, envisioned two alternative paths to human excellence and consummate happiness: the intellectual life of the philosopher-scientist and the social life of the politician. It’s not clear which road to the good life that Aristotle valued more.
All virtue-based moral systems focus on big questions such as: “What is the ‘Good Life? And “How do I go about living the ‘Good Life?” Therefore, they tend to focus on how to live one’s life, over the long run, rather than how to address particular issues that pop up at any given time. In short, virtue-based systems focus on character development within harmonious communities. These systems also tend to rely on moral exemplars, or role models. Once a person has internalized the virtue of kindness, then that person will exemplify that virtue in his/her actions.
Virtue-based moral systems also differentiate between virtues (good behavior) and vices (bad behavior). Ultimately, non-secular virtue-based theories differentiate between virtues and vices based on religious authorities, usually traced back to the authority of the Bible and/or its official interpreters. The Christian authorities have identified faith, hope, and charity as its primary virtues. If you pursue these ideals over the course of your lifetime, you’ll lead a “good life.”
Aristotle believed moral virtue consists in choosing the mean between the extremes of excess and deficiency within any given sphere of action. The vice of excess consists in choosing too much of a good thing and the vice of deficiency consists of not enough. Excellence is found midway between the two. For example, the virtue of bravery can be found midway between the vices of cowardice and foolhardiness. Today bravery is most often confused with foolhardiness. Obviously, an excellent army must have brave soldiers that are not afraid to die. But the purpose of going to war is to kill the soldiers in the opposing. An army of foolhardy soldiers will not last any longer than an army of cowards.
Moral virtue, according to Aristotle, is a character trait; a disposition of an individual to act in a certain way, under certain circumstances. These circumstances usually involve how we respond to emotional states via the exercise of reason. These habits or dispositions are cultivated via social and political institutions, especially institutions of education. The idea is to encourage desirable habitual behaviors (virtuous) behavior and discourage undesirable (vicious) behaviors. The actual standard of the virtue of courage varies between individuals and in different kinds of situations involving fear. For example, under conditions of war, the standard of courage would be different for soldiers and policemen, on the one hand, and civilians on the other. I’m sure Aristotle would have argued that men are more likely to be courageous than women, however, I think that’s wrong. It would be irrational to expect soldiers and civilians to act the same way under battle conditions. There are dangerous situations in war where certain responses are indicative of a foolhardy character. Courageous soldiers retreat in those situations. There are also situations where cowardly soldiers retreat, without just cause.
Moral education must begin at an early age and consists in developing the habit of choosing the mean between the extremes. Moral character is, therefore, cultivated in children by teaching them to emulate the behavior of virtuous adults. A child becomes virtuous when he/she habitually does the right thing and experiences pleasure upon doing it. Although knowing what the right thing to do is a necessary condition for virtue, it is not sufficient. You must also be able to “do the right thing.” Hence, Aristotle made a distinction between virtue and mere continence, or “weakness of the will.” An incontinent person knows the right thing to do, but is unable to do it because he/she is driven more by base feelings than reason. A continent person knows the right thing to do and even succeeds in doing it, but he/she does not feel pleasure upon doing it. In contrast, a virtuous person is not driven by base feelings and therefore feels good upon doing the right thing. An adult habitually prone toward excess or deficiency has a vicious character and will always act that way. Aristotle did not believe that vicious adults could be easily rehabilitated into virtuous adults. Send the bad guys to prison in order to protect us from their excesses, and to enforce justice. But don’t waste time and effort trying to rehabilitate them. That's why both Plato and Aristotle were advocates of rigorous childhood moral education.
The Greeks favored a republican form of government, modeled after the Greek city-states where the early communitarian philosophers like Plato and Aristotle lived. Republicanism according to the Ancient Greeks requires the cultivation of a common set of virtues, or character traits among its citizens. So in contrast to liberal democracies where "the right precedes the good," in a republic, "the good precedes the right." Republican communitarians, therefore, seek to promote standards of excellence consistent with the good of the whole community. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics was probably the first systematic exposition of a secular virtue-based ethical system. Here are a few more tidbits.
It is important to note that Aristotle is a hedonist (of a sort) and therefore, he thought that the end or goal of all deliberate human action is pleasure, or happiness. Not pleasure in the immediate present but pleasure over the course of one's entire lifetime. A good person experiences pleasure at the right time, place, and degree. Aristotle also distinguished between higher pleasures and lower pleasures. Lower pleasures (eating) are those pleasures that animals are capable of enjoying, while higher pleasures (reading philosophy) are pleasures that can only be appreciated by rational human beings. Rationality, unfortunately, is not distributed equally among human beings. Some of us are only capable of experiencing the lower pleasures, while others (usually the upper classes) can experience the higher pleasures.
While the Greeks favored Aristocracy as a form of government, some recent communitarians advocate cultivating character traits that are essential for participation in democratic self-government. For example, they argue that democracies must cultivate civic virtues such as friendship and caring in children in order to prepare them to cooperate in a communal setting. They argue that when children are raised in a culture based on unbridled self-interest, meaningful communal relationships become difficult to sustain.
Finally, virtue-based moral systems share one common feature with teleological and deontological moral systems: they are subject to human inquiry. Therefore, there is a lot of variation within that broad framework. There is very little consensus among virtue-based ethicists as to the nature of the Good Life, what specific virtues comprise the Good life, and how to go about teaching virtue. However, don’t get me wrong! This is not intended as an indictment of virtue-based moral systems, but rather a more general observation pertaining to all moral systems. As I stated from the very beginning of this book: Do not fall for the now fashionable argument that living the good life is easy, or that the study of ethics is easy. You can spend your entire lifetime questioning and answering these kinds of questions, and as you grow older you will no doubt change your mind many times over. Despite all this, I do think that moral inquiry will invariably revolve around the moral theories and principles emphasized in this book.
First of all, all virtue-based systems tend elevate community over individuals. Therefore, they tend more toward communitarianism than individualism. Secular virtue-based systems usually identify communities with political regimes. In the case of the Greeks, it was the city-state. Judeo-Christian non-secular virtue-based systems theorists identify with religious communities.
For both the non-secular and secular traditions, the virtue of something refers to its excellence: something that performs its function well. So anything subject to degrees (good, better, and best etc.) has its virtue. Hence, virtue determines status within a prescriptive hierarchy. Although we can talk about the virtue of a specific kind of computer over others, the Greeks most often referred to virtue as excellence of human character and behavior. Aristotle differentiated between two spheres of human activity that are governed by virtue: the intellectual sphere and the social or political sphere. Intellectual virtues reflect excellence of thought (wisdom etc), while moral virtues reflect excellence of human behavior (courage etc.) Hence, Aristotle, a hedonist, envisioned two alternative paths to human excellence and consummate happiness: the intellectual life of the philosopher-scientist and the social life of the politician. It’s not clear which road to the good life that Aristotle valued more.
All virtue-based moral systems focus on big questions such as: “What is the ‘Good Life? And “How do I go about living the ‘Good Life?” Therefore, they tend to focus on how to live one’s life, over the long run, rather than how to address particular issues that pop up at any given time. In short, virtue-based systems focus on character development within harmonious communities. These systems also tend to rely on moral exemplars, or role models. Once a person has internalized the virtue of kindness, then that person will exemplify that virtue in his/her actions.
Virtue-based moral systems also differentiate between virtues (good behavior) and vices (bad behavior). Ultimately, non-secular virtue-based theories differentiate between virtues and vices based on religious authorities, usually traced back to the authority of the Bible and/or its official interpreters. The Christian authorities have identified faith, hope, and charity as its primary virtues. If you pursue these ideals over the course of your lifetime, you’ll lead a “good life.”
Aristotle believed moral virtue consists in choosing the mean between the extremes of excess and deficiency within any given sphere of action. The vice of excess consists in choosing too much of a good thing and the vice of deficiency consists of not enough. Excellence is found midway between the two. For example, the virtue of bravery can be found midway between the vices of cowardice and foolhardiness. Today bravery is most often confused with foolhardiness. Obviously, an excellent army must have brave soldiers that are not afraid to die. But the purpose of going to war is to kill the soldiers in the opposing. An army of foolhardy soldiers will not last any longer than an army of cowards.
Below is a chart of Aristotelian virtues, their
respective spheres of action and their corresponding vices.
ARISTOTELIAN
VIRTUES AND VICES
SPHERE OF ACTION
|
VICE OF DEFICIENCY
|
MEAN OR VIRTUE
|
VICE OF EXCESS
|
Fear
|
cowardice
|
courage
|
foolhardiness
|
Pleasure and Pain
|
insensibility
|
temperance
|
self-indulgence
|
Acquisition (minor)
|
tight wad
|
liberality
|
spendthrift
or prodigality
|
Acquisition (major)
|
undue
humility
|
pride or proper
ambition
|
undue
vanity
|
Anger
|
unirascibility
|
patience or
good temper
|
hotheadedness
|
Self-Expression
|
Self
deprecating
|
truthfulness
|
boastfulness
|
Conversation
|
boorishness
|
wittiness
|
buffoonery
|
Social Conduct
|
cantankerous
|
friendliness
|
obsequiousness
|
Exhibition
|
shamelessness
|
modesty
|
shyness
|
Indignation
|
spitefulness
|
righteous
indignation
|
envy
|
Moral virtue, according to Aristotle, is a character trait; a disposition of an individual to act in a certain way, under certain circumstances. These circumstances usually involve how we respond to emotional states via the exercise of reason. These habits or dispositions are cultivated via social and political institutions, especially institutions of education. The idea is to encourage desirable habitual behaviors (virtuous) behavior and discourage undesirable (vicious) behaviors. The actual standard of the virtue of courage varies between individuals and in different kinds of situations involving fear. For example, under conditions of war, the standard of courage would be different for soldiers and policemen, on the one hand, and civilians on the other. I’m sure Aristotle would have argued that men are more likely to be courageous than women, however, I think that’s wrong. It would be irrational to expect soldiers and civilians to act the same way under battle conditions. There are dangerous situations in war where certain responses are indicative of a foolhardy character. Courageous soldiers retreat in those situations. There are also situations where cowardly soldiers retreat, without just cause.
Moral education must begin at an early age and consists in developing the habit of choosing the mean between the extremes. Moral character is, therefore, cultivated in children by teaching them to emulate the behavior of virtuous adults. A child becomes virtuous when he/she habitually does the right thing and experiences pleasure upon doing it. Although knowing what the right thing to do is a necessary condition for virtue, it is not sufficient. You must also be able to “do the right thing.” Hence, Aristotle made a distinction between virtue and mere continence, or “weakness of the will.” An incontinent person knows the right thing to do, but is unable to do it because he/she is driven more by base feelings than reason. A continent person knows the right thing to do and even succeeds in doing it, but he/she does not feel pleasure upon doing it. In contrast, a virtuous person is not driven by base feelings and therefore feels good upon doing the right thing. An adult habitually prone toward excess or deficiency has a vicious character and will always act that way. Aristotle did not believe that vicious adults could be easily rehabilitated into virtuous adults. Send the bad guys to prison in order to protect us from their excesses, and to enforce justice. But don’t waste time and effort trying to rehabilitate them. That's why both Plato and Aristotle were advocates of rigorous childhood moral education.
The Greeks favored a republican form of government, modeled after the Greek city-states where the early communitarian philosophers like Plato and Aristotle lived. Republicanism according to the Ancient Greeks requires the cultivation of a common set of virtues, or character traits among its citizens. So in contrast to liberal democracies where "the right precedes the good," in a republic, "the good precedes the right." Republican communitarians, therefore, seek to promote standards of excellence consistent with the good of the whole community. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics was probably the first systematic exposition of a secular virtue-based ethical system. Here are a few more tidbits.
It is important to note that Aristotle is a hedonist (of a sort) and therefore, he thought that the end or goal of all deliberate human action is pleasure, or happiness. Not pleasure in the immediate present but pleasure over the course of one's entire lifetime. A good person experiences pleasure at the right time, place, and degree. Aristotle also distinguished between higher pleasures and lower pleasures. Lower pleasures (eating) are those pleasures that animals are capable of enjoying, while higher pleasures (reading philosophy) are pleasures that can only be appreciated by rational human beings. Rationality, unfortunately, is not distributed equally among human beings. Some of us are only capable of experiencing the lower pleasures, while others (usually the upper classes) can experience the higher pleasures.
While the Greeks favored Aristocracy as a form of government, some recent communitarians advocate cultivating character traits that are essential for participation in democratic self-government. For example, they argue that democracies must cultivate civic virtues such as friendship and caring in children in order to prepare them to cooperate in a communal setting. They argue that when children are raised in a culture based on unbridled self-interest, meaningful communal relationships become difficult to sustain.
Finally, virtue-based moral systems share one common feature with teleological and deontological moral systems: they are subject to human inquiry. Therefore, there is a lot of variation within that broad framework. There is very little consensus among virtue-based ethicists as to the nature of the Good Life, what specific virtues comprise the Good life, and how to go about teaching virtue. However, don’t get me wrong! This is not intended as an indictment of virtue-based moral systems, but rather a more general observation pertaining to all moral systems. As I stated from the very beginning of this book: Do not fall for the now fashionable argument that living the good life is easy, or that the study of ethics is easy. You can spend your entire lifetime questioning and answering these kinds of questions, and as you grow older you will no doubt change your mind many times over. Despite all this, I do think that moral inquiry will invariably revolve around the moral theories and principles emphasized in this book.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)