Review for
Politics and the Life Sciences.
Cass R.
Sunstein, On Freedom (Princeton
University Press: 2019)
127 pp. ISBN: 978-0-691-19115-7. Hardcover $12.95.
Ronald F, White, Ph.D., Professor of Philosophy, Mount
St. Joseph University.
Areas of Expertise: Social and Political Philosophy,
Ethics
Cass R. Sunstein is
founder and director of Harvard University’s Program on Behavior Economics and
Public Policy. He is also a world-renowned legal scholar, and an
extraordinarily prolific author. He is best known as the co-author (with
Richard H. Thaler) of the best-selling book Nudge:
Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth, and Happiness (2009). Since then,
Sunstein has authored and/or co-authored countless journal articles and at
least three other books that reiterate, and/or expand upon what Sunstein and
Thaler originally referred to as “Libertarian Paternalism.” Those three books include: Why Nudge: The Politics of Libertarian
Paternalism (Yale: 2014), The Ethics
of Influence: Government in the Age of Behavioral Science (Cambridge: 2016); and Human Agency and Behavioral Economics: Nudging Fast and Slow (Palgrave
MacMillan: 2017). It is noteworthy that these three accounts of Libertarian
Paternalism build a common conceptual framework and cover similar ground. Back in 2018, I contributed to a multi-authored
forum for PLS that explored the
framework we entitled “Nudge Science.” (White 2018) This review will build upon
the conceptual framework explored in those review essays, especially my introductory
essay. Henceforth, I’ll refer to the collective content of those four earlier works,
as “Nudge Science.”
First of all, it is
important to note that On Freedom is
a tiny, hard-cover book: 5 x 7 inches with 118 pages of narrative. And like all
of Sunstein’s books, it is well-crafted, easy-to- read, interesting, and targets
both scholarly and popular audiences. It is priced by Princeton University
Press at $12.95 and available at Amazon for $9.58. This review will address two
main questions. First, how much of On Freedom elaborates upon and/or
recapitulates the conceptual framework previously published in Nudge Science; and
how much (if anything) is altogether new and a worthwhile addition to that body
of work? Second, in light of these first
two answers, who (if anyone) would be interested in this book and what (if
anything) would they get out of it?
Obviously, the title On Freedom is in direct reference to
John Stuart Mill’s classic work On
Liberty (1859), which is widely regarded as the primary source of anti-paternalism
within the Classical Liberal tradition. For Mill and his libertarian followers,
legally restricting the liberty of a rational, and competent adult, in order to
provide an unwanted benefit and/or prevent self-induced harm is a priori unacceptable. Nudge Science
(including On Freedom) revisits that
argument and asks the question: Under
what circumstances (if any) can a liberty-loving, self-governed society deploy
bans, mandates, and/or nudges to promote/advance the welfare of rational
competent adults without their consent? Nudge Science has consistently argued that
there is more room for paternalistic intervention within the Classical Liberal tradition
than most libertarians are willing to acknowledge.
So how do we go about morally evaluating the ethics of governmental
actions? In The Ethics of Influence,
Sunstein argued that government actions must be evaluated in light of four,
often-conflicting values. That is, by asking whether the action under
consideration…”increases welfare,
promotes autonomy, respects dignity, and promotes self-government.” (p. 53) On Freedom focuses primarily on the moral
conflict between his principles of autonomy (freedom) and welfare conflict
(well-being). Mill and most Classical
Liberals argue that individual freedom of choice necessarily promotes human
well-being of both individuals and the collective. After all, rational,
competent adults would to be the best judge of what will or will not promote
our own well-being; and, therefore we be allowed to go our own way, so long as we
do not harm others. (p. 3) On Freedom
challenges several key aspects of that libertarian argument.
Nudge Science reexamines freedom
of choice in light of the recent findings of social science, namely, that all
of our “choices” are influenced (if not determined) by choice architecture, erected by either Mother Nature, and/or by
individuals and groups within our socio-political environment. Our vulnerability
to the influence of competing choice architects has been enhanced by
advancements in behavioral economics, especially the discovery of “behavioral
biases” and other fallacies that predispose us to make choices based on
pre-determined patterns, including present
bias (our natural tendency to pursue our immediate, short-term personal
well-being, often at the expense of our long-term well-being. So, whether we are
consciously aware of it or not, we are constantly being “nudged,” often by competing
choice architects. Not all of those
architects seek to advance our personal welfare. Many nudge us one way or
another in order to benefit themselves, their family, and/or friends. Sunstein
argues that, if all of our choices have been nudged by choice architects, and
if many of those nudges are hostile to our welfare, then welfare advancing political
nudges are, obviously, morally preferable to welfare invading nudges.
On Freedom, therefore,
argues that under conditions of self-government, the state can (and ought to)
nudge us toward advancing our personal welfare. But this raises a number of
longstanding libertarian issues. How can well-meaning choice architects know
whether their paternalistic interventions will (in fact) advance our well-being?
Sunstein argues that the value of
welfare enhancing nudges can only be assessed by the intended beneficiary. But
when? Before the benefits are experienced or after? If “after,” how long
after? Thus Sunstein points out that the
“as judged by themselves” principle contains hidden complexities. For example, prior
to being nudged, drug and alcohol addicts might object to being nudged away
from those freedom-reducing addictions, but most of us would not, subsequently,
object to having been nudged away from those addictions, and/or having been nudged
toward eating healthy foods, exercising regularly, donating our organs, or
saving toward retirement.
So what, if anything, does On
Freedom contribute to the lexicon of Nudge Science? Sunstein introduces two
innovative features: one is stylistic, the other more substantive.
Stylistically, On Freedom is different
from his earlier books, in that he employs several expository case studies to
reveal hidden complexities. He also uses several illustrative examples drawn
from classic literature. His recent interest in drawing upon works of popular
culture is reflected in another recent best-selling book, The World According to Star Wars (2016). Neither of these stylistic innovations are particularly
problematic. However, at least some scientists and philosophers will be
less-than enthusiastic about his expository references to the arts and
humanities.
On Freedom’s
more substantive innovation consists in introducing a new set of “navigational
metaphors” intended to clarify and/or expand upon his earlier “architectural
metaphors.” As Sunstein put it:
“Obstacles to navigability have been the great blind spot in the Western
philosophical tradition?” (p.2) Therefore, the over-riding question addressed
in On Freedom is whether the
institutions of democratic government can effectively help us navigate through
the architectural maze of modern life without violating our personal autonomy. He argues that the effectiveness of our
individual pursuit of well-being requires more than freedom of choice. We must
also be able to “navigate” our way through an ever-growing maze of
architectural variables.
At first glance, Sunstein’s
navigational metaphors, such as “navigation” and “navigators,” seem to elucidate
Nudge Science. Suppose, based on my own current interests, I decide to take a
vacation in Hawaii. I know where I want
to go, but lack the navigational knowledge/skills necessary to get there. Thus,
I might willingly choose to employ an airplane pilot, rather than, say a cruise
ship pilot. But to what degree does life in general resemble a voyage? The expanded use of navigational metaphors suggest
that life is about “going somewhere,” (either literally or figuratively); that
we know where we want to go; and that we willingly employ skilled navigators to
help us get there. So far, so good. However, the closer we look at these
navigational metaphors, knowledge problems arise. After all, there are (in fact) more-skilled
and less-skilled navigators, and we do not always know how to distinguish between
the two. Even if our chosen navigators are (in fact) skilled, we may not know
whether they intend to employ their navigational skills in order to advance or
undermine our individual welfare and/or the welfare of others.
Those navigational metaphors
begin to break down when various kinds of institutionalized navigators (public/
private) not only nudge us toward our chosen destination, but also surreptitiously
choose “where we want to go.” Most of us would not object to be reminded of the
likelihood of volcanic activity, in Hawaii, which may or may not influence us
to change vacation plans. But those
metaphors irrevocably break down when that navigator possesses the knowledge
and ability to surreptitiously “nudge” us toward an alternative destination. To
what extent do those navigators violate our autonomy when they nudge us toward that
alternative destination, even if it might improve my well-being? Do those
actions contradict the very concept of a navigator?
Sunstein argues that in a
democratic society, navigators often violate our autonomy when they employ the
coercive power of legally enforced bans and mandates to increase our
self-regarding welfare interests. So while coercive bans and mandates can play
a role in a liberty-loving society, they must be limited to preventing harm to
others. However, according to Sunstein, welfare-enhancing nudges are
non-coercive, autonomy-preserving, and morally acceptable. However, when that navigator violates our autonomy
by taking us places where we do not want to go, in order to advance our
personal welfare, we might subsequently prefer “by our own lights” that
alternative welfare-enhancing destination. Life can be either easy or difficult
to navigate, depending on choice architecture that underlies our choices.
Helpful choice architecture simplifies navigation. His overall claim is that
government can play a role in “nudging” us toward decisions that advance our
individual well-being.
So what, exactly, does the
Sunstein’s use of navigational metaphors contribute to Nudge Science? Do those
metaphors elucidate or obfuscate the autonomy-welfare conflict? Most Nudge
Scholars will agree that, beyond the introduction of those navigational
metaphors, there is not a lot of new philosophical analysis and/or research
within its pages. Pundits will question
whether mixing those “architectural” and “navigational” metaphors elucidates or
obfuscates Nudge Science.
So despite the fact that
some critics will ultimately object to its stylistic and/or substantive
innovations, most audiences will appreciate and benefit reading On Freedom. Scholars who are actively
engaged in Nudge Science will appreciate it as an up-to-date summary of those four
previous works that comprise “Nudge Science.” Social scientists, philosophers, and
readers of popular science, who have not yet explored Nudge Science, will certainly
benefit from On Freedom, as a concise,
well-written, up-to-date introduction. In the final analysis, although this
little book really does not break new scholarly ground, it will serve as a
brief, inexpensive, and well-crafted summary of the current state of Nudge
Science.
References
C. R. Sunstein and R.
Thaler, Nudge: Improving Decisions about
Health, Wealth, and Happiness (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2008).
C.R. Sunstein, Why Nudge: The Politics of
Libertarian Paternalism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2014).
C.R. Sunstein, The Ethics of Influence: Government in the
Age of Behavioral Science. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2016)
C.R. Sunstein, Human Agency and Behavioral Economics:
Nudging Fast and Slow (Switzerland: Palgrave McMillan, 2017).
C.R. Sunstein, The World According to Star Wars (New
York: Harper Collins, 2016)
J.S. Mill, On Liberty (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett,
1978), 1859; repr.
R.F. White, Eliah J.
White, Charles Kroncke, Edward Sankowski, David Vanderburgh. “Cass R.
Sunstein’s “Nudge Science”: Ethics, Influence, and Public Policy” Politics and the Life Sciences, Volume
37, Issue 1, 2018, pp.113-.
R.F. White, “An
Introduction to Nudge Science and the Ethics of Influence” (in) R.F. White
et.al “Cass R. Sunstein’s “Nudge Science”: Ethics, Influence, and Public
Policy” Politics and the Life Sciences,
Volume 37, Issue 1, 2018, pp.113-118.
No comments:
Post a Comment